
Abstract
This article offers fresh insights into the discussions of Artificial General Intelligence (AGI), drawing on Arthur Herman’s “The Cave and the Light.” It juxtaposes Plato’s exploration of abstract forms with Aristotle’s focus on empirical evidence, revealing their nuanced impact on contemporary AGI debates. The piece highlights the dual role of human intelligence in AGI as both a method and a subject of study while exploring the contributions of Kurt Gödel and Alan Turing. Gödel’s skepticism and Turing’s optimism about machine capabilities reflect the depth and complexity of AGI development. The article also addresses AGI’s impossible machine and self-design loop paradoxes.
Ultimately, it illuminates the timeless struggle revived within AGI, underscored by classical philosophy, emphasizing the ongoing tension between Plato’s pursuit of the ideal and Aristotle’s grounding on the tangible.
The Impossible Machine: Good’s Paradox
As the advent of Artificial General Intelligence (AGI) draws closer, a pivotal question arises: Can AGI truly surpass the general problem-solving abilities of humans? While advancements like ChatGPT have marked significant strides in AI, AGI suggests a transformational leap forward — a scope of cognitive abilities that extends beyond even the specialized nature of human intellect.
The essence of ‘general’ in AGI is crucial. It denotes an intelligence not confined to specialization but universally adaptable, excelling across diverse problem-solving domains. This prompts a question: Is it possible to create machines that rival or surpass humans in solving problems across varied fields?
The paradox introduced by Jack Good in 1948, during his collaboration with Alan Turing, becomes increasingly pertinent in this context. Good’s paradox delves into the core distinction between human and machine intelligence, unveiling a fundamental contradiction:
No machine could be designed to resolve every problem humans can, implying a limitation in machine design.
Yet, considering humans as a type of ‘machine’ introduces a logical inconsistency.
In this view, humans emerge as an ‘impossible machine’ — capable of solving problems beyond the capacity of any machine, including themselves. To resolve the paradox, either humans possess unique problem-solving abilities that machines can never replicate, or there exists the potential to develop machines that can solve problems as effectively as humans, the idea behind AGI.
The Self-Design Loop: The Creation Paradox
Yet, this notion of AGI’s machine superiority introduces a different paradoxical scenario. If we hypothesize that AGI could solve problems beyond human capabilities, including the creation of AGI itself, we are then confronted with the ‘self-design loop.’ This concept suggests that AGI might inherently possess, or even surpass, our capacity to create such advanced machines, thus leading to a logical conundrum.
This scenario appears to conflict with the principle of causality, where every effect must have a cause. In a self-design loop, machines would paradoxically need to exist before their own creation in order to initiate their design, thereby defying the fundamental principles of causality. It’s crucial to acknowledge that, as of now, human creators are behind all AI systems that are claimed to possess some level of autonomy.
Historically, humans have not been concerned about our inventions surpassing us in specific capacities: cars outrunning us, buildings outlasting us, and computers out-calculating us. These have extended our physical and mental capabilities. However, AGI presents a unique challenge: it is envisioned to surpass all aspects of our thinking and problem-solving abilities, including the capability to create AGI itself. This leads to a paradox where the creation is designed to outperform the creator’s intellectual abilities, encompassing even the act of creation itself
Gödel and Turing: The Architects of Modern AI Debate
As we delve into the complexities of the AGI conundrum presented by Good’s Paradox, it becomes evident that the roots of this debate extend into the profound insights of two pivotal figures in the history of logic and computing: Kurt Gödel and Alan Turing. Their distinct perspectives mirror the dual aspects of Good’s Paradox.
Kurt Gödel, with his groundbreaking Incompleteness Theorems, introduced a layer of skepticism about the limits of formal systems, including those underpinning computational machines. His work suggests that elements of human cognition might always elude machines bound by their programmed logic, highlighting the unique, non-mechanical facets of human thought.
In contrast, Alan Turing’s optimistic outlook, as embodied in the Turing Test, proposes a different view. Turing hypothesized that machines could one day exhibit behavior indistinguishable from human intelligence. This hypothesis offers a counterpoint to Gödel’s skepticism, suggesting a future where artificial and human intelligence might converge, or where the former could even surpass the latter.
This optimistic view from Turing leads us to a pivotal question in the AGI debate: Could Turing’s belief in the potential of machines have been overly ambitious? Envisioning a future where machine intelligence could equal or even surpass human capabilities, Turing laid a cornerstone for the pursuit of AGI. However, Gödel’s skepticism, combined with the inherent contradictions highlighted by the ‘impossible machine’ and the ‘self-design loop,’ casts doubt on this vision.
Reflecting on these contrasting viewpoints raises questions about the nature of human and machine intelligence. If Gödel’s perspective, emphasizing the unique and potentially insurmountable aspects of human cognition, holds, then Turing’s hypothesis about machine intelligence reaching or exceeding human intelligence encounters philosophical and logical hurdles.
This contemporary debate, reminiscent of the philosophical dialogues between Plato and Aristotle, underscores the timeless nature of the questions we face in the development of AGI.
Plato vs. Aristotle: The Cave and the Light

In the intellectual sphere of ancient Athens stood two foundational institutions of philosophical thought: Aristotle’s Lyceum and Plato’s Academy. Arthur Herman’s ‘The Cave and the Light’ (2013) delves into the enduring legacies of these philosophers, shedding light on their contrasting approaches to knowledge and reality. Although Herman’s work doesn’t directly address Artificial General Intelligence (AGI), the philosophical foundations laid by Plato and Aristotle are insightful for understanding the modern debates in this field.
Central to Plato’s philosophy is his famous ‘Allegory of the Cave.’ This allegory, reflecting his exploration of ideal forms, describes prisoners in a cave who see only shadows on a wall, unaware that these are mere reflections of real objects. For Plato, the cave symbolizes the world of sensory experience — a flawed and illusory reflection of the true, ideal world beyond the physical. The journey from the cave into the light represents the philosopher’s pursuit of knowledge and understanding of these ideal forms.
In contrast, Aristotle’s philosophy is deeply rooted in tangible reality. Unlike Plato’s focus on abstract forms in a separate realm, Aristotle concentrated on studying the physical world and its processes. Herman depicts Aristotle as emphasizing empirical evidence and observation, considering knowledge to be derived from the tangible and practical aspects of the world.
To summarize, Plato’s quest for knowledge in the abstract realm leads him to seek light beyond the cave, while Aristotle’s inquiry for truth in the observable world guides him to find light within the cave.
Philosophical Echoes in AGI
Central to both Plato’s and Aristotle’s philosophies is the crucial role of human reason or intelligence — for Plato, it’s a tool to apprehend abstract Forms, and for Aristotle, a method to study the tangible world. However, in AGI, human intelligence itself becomes the focus of study. AGI is modeled after the ‘Form’ of human intelligence in the Platonic sense, while also being a tangible subject of empirical study and observation, as per the Aristotelian tradition.
The dual nature of human intelligence, both as a tool and an entity, positions AGI as an invention crafted ‘in our image,’ illustrating our inseparable bond with this creation.
The dual nature of human intelligence, both as a tool and an entity, positions AGI as an invention crafted ‘in our image,’ illustrating our inseparable bond with this creation. This concept is echoed in Gödel’s insights, emphasizing the evolving and self-reflective nature of human thought. Gödel articulated this idea, stating
Mind, in its use, is not static, but constantly developing, i.e., we understand abstract terms more and more precisely as we go on using them, and more abstract terms enter our understanding (Copland, 2013, 192).
Turing’s vision adds another dimension, emphasizing the empirical aspect of AGI. He observed,
There would be no question of triumphing simultaneously over all machines. In short, then, there might be men cleverer than any given machine, but then there might be other machines cleverer again, and so on (Copland, 2013, 194).
The views of Gödel and Turing provide a comprehensive framework for approaching AGI. From the human perspective, influenced by Gödel’s skepticism, AGI can be envisioned not as a race towards a static finish line but as an ongoing pursuit closely aligned with the ever-expanding scope of human intelligence, further enhanced by AGI itself. On the other hand, from the machine’s perspective, as influenced by Turing, AGI’s advancement will involve human-in-the-loop validation, where human intelligence, as mirrored in machines, is continually tested and enhanced.
Within this framework, the logical challenges of AGI, specifically the ‘impossible machine’ and ‘self-design loop’ paradoxes, can be addressed:
- Viewing the ideal ‘Form’ of human intelligence as static leads to the concept of the impossible machine — a theoretical entity that fails to account for the evolving nature of human cognition by attempting to encapsulate it in a fixed state.
- Mistaking the Platonic ideal of human intelligence for its empirical approximations can lead to the belief in an AGI capable of a self-design loop, thereby neglecting the essential role of human intervention in its iterations.
Acknowledging these oversights reshapes our view of AGI. It emerges as an evolving extension of human problem-solving and creativity, inseparable from its human origin.
Conclusion: The Timeless Struggle
The divergent perceptions of Plato and Aristotle on the cave and the light might continue to shape the development of AI and the path to AGI, much like their philosophies have historically influenced the course leading to modern civilization.
Without Aristotle’s emphasis on the tangible and real, our most profound ideas risk remaining confined to the realm of theory, never realizing practical AI applications. Similarly, lacking the visionaries who embrace Plato’s ideal forms — those who urge us to see beyond the immediately observable — our AI advancements may never acquire the spark needed to evolve past basic functionalities toward AGI.
Plato’s daring establishes a vision, expanding the horizons of possibility. Meanwhile, Aristotle’s relentless advances drive tangible progress. It’s this timeless struggle, the absence of either perspective, that underlines the importance of both. Together, they highlight the enduring relevance of these ancient philosophical debates in our modern quest for AGI.
References
1. Copland, J. B., Posy, C. J., & Shagrir, O. (2013). Computability: Turing, Gödel, Church, and Beyond (Kindle ed.). The MIT Press.
2. Herman, A. (2013). The Cave and the Light: Plato Versus Aristotle, and the Struggle for the Soul of Western Civilization. Random House.